Skip to main content

Sleeping Beauty Paradox

Q: Sleeping Beauty (SB) has volunteered for a test. The test is structured as follows. On a Sunday SB is put to sleep and after that a coin is tossed. If the coin
  1. Comes up HEADS, SB is awoken on the following day (Monday) and asked her belief in the probability that the toss came up heads. The experiment ends.
  2. Comes up TAILS, same as above except that at the end of the question her memory of the waking event and question is wiped out and she is awoken the next day (Tuesday) and asked the same question. The experiment ends.
The question is, when SB is awoken, what is SB's belief in the probability that it was heads. Note: At any given time, SB has no way to tell if it is a Monday or a Tuesday.


A:  While it is tempting (and there are some arguments out there) to say the probability is \(\frac{1}{2}\), the reality isn't so. Here is why. Take a look at the following table.

The "X" indicates the situations when SB wakes up. Given that SB does not know which day of the week it is, she would guess \( P(Heads) = \frac{1}{3}\). If she knew that the day was a Monday, then we need only consider the Monday column and \(P(Heads) = \frac{1}{2}\). Likewise, if she knew it was a Tuesday then \(P(Tails) = 1\).


If you are looking to buy some books in probability here are some of the best books to learn the art of Probability

Here are a few
Fifty Challenging Problems in Probability with Solutions (Dover Books on Mathematics)
This book is a great compilation that covers quite a bit of puzzles. What I like about these puzzles are that they are all tractable and don't require too much advanced mathematics to solve.

Introduction to Algorithms
This is a book on algorithms, some of them are probabilistic. But the book is a must have for students, job candidates even full time engineers & data scientists

Introduction to Probability Theory

An Introduction to Probability Theory and Its Applications, Vol. 1, 3rd Edition

The Probability Tutoring Book: An Intuitive Course for Engineers and Scientists (and Everyone Else!)

Introduction to Probability, 2nd Edition

The Mathematics of Poker
Good read. Overall Poker/Blackjack type card games are a good way to get introduced to probability theory

Let There Be Range!: Crushing SSNL/MSNL No-Limit Hold'em Games
Easily the most expensive book out there. So if the item above piques your interest and you want to go pro, go for it.

Quantum Poker
Well written and easy to read mathematics. For the Poker beginner.


Bundle of Algorithms in Java, Third Edition, Parts 1-5: Fundamentals, Data Structures, Sorting, Searching, and Graph Algorithms (3rd Edition) (Pts. 1-5)
An excellent resource (students/engineers/entrepreneurs) if you are looking for some code that you can take and implement directly on the job.

Understanding Probability: Chance Rules in Everyday Life A bit pricy when compared to the first one, but I like the look and feel of the text used. It is simple to read and understand which is vital especially if you are trying to get into the subject

Data Mining: Practical Machine Learning Tools and Techniques, Third Edition (The Morgan Kaufmann Series in Data Management Systems) This one is a must have if you want to learn machine learning. The book is beautifully written and ideal for the engineer/student who doesn't want to get too much into the details of a machine learned approach but wants a working knowledge of it. There are some great examples and test data in the text book too.

Discovering Statistics Using R
This is a good book if you are new to statistics & probability while simultaneously getting started with a programming language. The book supports R and is written in a casual humorous way making it an easy read. Great for beginners. Some of the data on the companion website could be missing.



Comments

  1. While the answer is indeed 1/3, your argument is (barely) not right. It requires one more trivial step. But the halfers, those who favor the 1/2 answer, will simply dismiss it citing that step as the reason. They usually dismiss it with that step as well, but they never say why. Because they can't.

    Instead of finding a flaw in the more explicit thirder reasoning, halfers claim that SB has no "new information" on which to base a change in the probability. But they never define what actually is necessary to do that, and it turns out you do have it.

    Anyway, the original argument is that IF you are told it is Monday, you should have equal confidence that the coin landed heads or tails. This means that P(Heads&Monday)=P(Tails&Monday). Similarly, IF you are told that the coin landed tails, you should have equal confidence that it is Monday or Tuesday. This means that P(Tails&Monday)=P(Tails&Tuesday). Since I've listed the three exclusive possibilities, and they must be equal, it follows that all equal to 1/3.

    The argument that directly contradicts the halfers is that, AT ANY TIME DURING THE EXPERIMENT, there are four possible combinations of day and coin, not three. Each has a prior probability to apply to a random moment of 1/4. Since she is awake, SB knows that the combination Tuesday&Heads is ruled out, so the updated probability for each of the other three is (1/4)/(1/4+1/4+1/4)=1/3.

    ReplyDelete
  2. The random experiment described in the beginning of your post consists of just a coin flip and there are only two possible outcomes (Heads or Tails). The "Tails and Monday", "Tails and Tuesday" events you employ are actually the same event (the outcome Tails). Hence, assuming a fair coin, P(Heads and Monday)=P(Heads)=1/2, P(Tails and Monday)= P(Tails and Tuesday)= P(Tails)=1/2.

    Please also consider the following variance of the Sleeping Beauty Problem:
    Instead of one person the experiment is conducted to 10^6 persons. All but one will be awoken only once, whereas a randomly selected individual will be awoken 10^12 times using some drug that erases the memory of previous awakenings. All participants are informed about this setup.
    Before they are put to sleep the probability that they are the selected one, as calculated by each individual, is 10^-6, hence, they consider it highly improbable to be awoken more than once. According to thirders’ arguments, once they wake up, they should believe that the probability of NOT being the selected one is about 10^-6, since if the experiment is repeated an infinite amount of times for each individual, for every 10^6 awakenings roughly 1 will be associated with not being selected. Thus, according to thirders, just because you wake up (which you now all along that is certainly going to happen), you should think that you are the selected one, which is completely irrational, leading to absurd conclusions by ignoring basic probability rules on independence and Bayesian updating.
    Another argument thirders usually employ, is the betting odds. Let’s assume that each time a person wakes up is offered the following bet: If they bet that they are the selected one and win they will gain 1$, whereas if they loose they will loose 1000$. They are also informed that in case they are indeed the selected one, although the bet will be offered at each awakening, only the first one is valid. According to thirders they should always take the bet (since they are almost certain that they are the selected one) with an expected gain of about 1$. According to halfers the expected loss is about 1000$ and they would never take the bet. I would very much like to bet a million dollars against 1 million thirders and gain 1 billion dollars (minus of course the 1001$ that I will not get from the selected one)

    ReplyDelete
  3. Halfers always find an (invalid) reason to dismiss variations that involve repetition or betting. So instead, I'm going to propose a different alternate version:

    Q: Sleeping Beauty (SB) has volunteered for a test. The test is structured as follows. On a Sunday SB is put to sleep in a room that is painted red. Sometime before Tuesday, a (fair) coin is tossed.

    1) On Monday she is wakened in the same room. ("Awoke" in all its forms is an intransitive verb. SB can't be "awoken," but she can be "wakened." Its frequent use in this problem demonstrates that the authors are being pedantic.) She is interviewed. Then her memory is erased.

    2) On Tuesday, if the coin comes up Heads, she is moved to a room that is painted blue. If it comes up Tails, she is left in the same room. Regardless of the coin, she is interviewed again.

    3) In each interview, she is asked her belief in the probability that the toss will/did come up heads.

    She can give different answers, depending on the color of the room she is in. What are they?

    Obviously, her answer should be 100% in a blue room. It isn't hard to show that it should be 33% in a red room. And it isn't hard to accept, either, because increasing the probability in the case she knows didn't happen must be offset with a decrease in the one she knows she is in.

    What people find hard to accept is that if she is in a red room, the problem is identical to your original. They can't reconcile the fact that not being able to know what happens on Tuesday after Heads is irrelevant if all she knows is that it is not Tuesday after Heads.

    ReplyDelete

Post a Comment

Popular posts from this blog

The Best Books to Learn Probability

If you are looking to buy some books in probability here are some of the best books to learn the art of Probability The Probability Tutoring Book: An Intuitive Course for Engineers and Scientists (and Everyone Else!) A good book for graduate level classes: has some practice problems in them which is a good thing. But that doesn't make this book any less of buy for the beginner. An Introduction to Probability Theory and Its Applications, Vol. 1, 3rd Edition This is a two volume book and the first volume is what will likely interest a beginner because it covers discrete probability. The book tends to treat probability as a theory on its own Discovering Statistics Using R This is a good book if you are new to statistics & probability while simultaneously getting started with a programming language. The book supports R and is written in a casual humorous way making it an easy read. Great for beginners. Some of the data on the companion website could be missing. Fifty Cha...

The Best Books for Linear Algebra

The following are some good books to own in the area of Linear Algebra. Linear Algebra (2nd Edition) This is the gold standard for linear algebra at an undergraduate level. This book has been around for quite sometime a great book to own. Linear Algebra: A Modern Introduction Good book if you want to learn more on the subject of linear algebra however typos in the text could be a problem. Linear Algebra (Dover Books on Mathematics) An excellent book to own if you are looking to get into, or want to understand linear algebra. Please keep in mind that you need to have some basic mathematical background before you can use this book. Linear Algebra Done Right (Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics) A great book that exposes the method of proof as it used in Linear Algebra. This book is not for the beginner though. You do need some prior knowledge of the basics at least. It would be a good add-on to an existing course you are doing in Linear Algebra. Linear Algebra, 4th Ed...

Fun with Uniform Random Numbers

Q: You have two uniformly random numbers x and y (meaning they can take any value between 0 and 1 with equal probability). What distribution does the sum of these two random numbers follow? What is the probability that their product is less than 0.5. The Probability Tutoring Book: An Intuitive Course for Engineers and Scientists A: Let z = x + y be the random variable whose distribution we want. Clearly z runs from 0 to 2. Let 'f' denote the uniform random distribution between [0,1]. An important point to understand is that f has a fixed value of 1 when x runs from 0 to 1 and its 0 otherwise. So the probability density for z, call it P(z) at any point is the product of f(y) and f(z-y), where y runs from 0 to 1. However in that range f(y) is equal to 1. So the above equation becomes From here on, it gets a bit tricky. Notice that the integral is a function of z. Let us take a look at how else we can simply the above integral. It is easy to see that f(z-y) = 1 when (...